UPDATE (May 15, 2022):
I started reading Buffalo shooter’s manifesto expecting the same eco-fascism/green nationalism type language we saw in the El Paso and Christchurch shooters’ manifestos and sure enough: “green nationalism is the only true nationalism” pic.twitter.com/Pbb81Y6EMj
— Tad DeLay (@taddelay) May 15, 2022
When remembered at all, Edward Abbey is mostly thought of as an environmentalist and anarchist but there is no gainsaying the racism and xenophobia on display in his 1983 essay, "Immigration and Liberal Taboos." The opinion piece was originally solicited by the New York Times, which ultimately declined to publish it -- or to pay him the customary kill fee. It was subsequently rejected by Harper's, The Atlantic, The New Republic, Rolling Stone, Newsweek, Mother Jones and Playboy before finally being published in the Phoenix New Times as “The Closing Door Policy.”
Various white nationalist blogs applaud what they view as Abbey's foresight and forthrightness regarding immigration, presumably oblivious to how those views relate to his ideas about wealth inequality, industrial development and authoritarianism. Conversely, Abbey fans on the left who seek to insulate his nature writing from the taint of his anti-immigrant bigotry ignore the way in which, as Michael Potts put it, "a xenophobic and racist image of the immigrant as pollution... map[s] cultural and ethnic prejudices on to an idealised landscape." (Dumping Grounds: Donald Trump, Edward Abbey and the Immigrant as Pollution) Abbey's admirers on both the right and the left thus resort either to blinkers or lame apologetic to redeem him for their political preferences.
My interpretation is that Abbey was a curmudgeon and contrarian whose intended target was liberal hypocrisy. Immigrants were merely "collateral damage" of his colorful diatribes. In the pursuit of being provocative, though, he revealed more than he bargained for about his prejudices. It is precisely this flawed complexity, though, that makes Abbey's writing a kind of Rosetta Stone for deciphering the dire social hieroglyphics of our time. Presumably, Abbey did not think of himself as racist. He was indignant when accused of racism. But the institutions of the society he grew up in transmit racism in their DNA.
The purported manifesto of the alleged El Paso terrorist, Patrick Crusius, contains passages that Alexander Kaufman at HuffPost and Natasha Lennard at The Intercept have labelled "eco-fascist." The manifesto author's "solution" to environmental degradation and resource depletion is to "get rid of enough people" so that "our way of life can become more sustainable."
Citing David Brooks, Jeffrey Tucker at the American Institute for Economic Education calls these views "anti-pluralist" and "anti-modern." More fundamentally, Tucker sees them as "anti-capitalist." Ironically, though, the manifesto makes no case for either fascist or anti-capitalist system change. Extermination is offered as a way of preserving the status quo in the face of corporations', governments' and the average American's unwillingness to change.
While the El Paso terrorist's manifesto is linked to and defined by a singular act of violence, Abbey's essay stands within a body of work that situates, elaborates, reinforces, qualifies and may or may not redeem its sins and omissions. Abbey's objection to industrial and population growth promoted by "cornucopia economists of the ever-expanding economy" is not a one-off aimed at immigrants but is a central theme of his writing. An image he repeats in several essays is of growth as cancerous madness. "Growth for the sake of growth is the ideology of the cancer cell," he wrote in "Arizona: How big is big enough?"
Actually, cancer cells don't have ideologies, which curiously makes Abbey's maxim more apt. Cancer cells neither know what they are doing nor ask why they are doing it. They just carry out the instructions in their mutated DNA. Furthermore, "growth" -- that is to say population growth – is never for the sake of population growth. It is presumably for the sake of raising the value of real estate, expanding markets for retail sales and providing a broader and deeper labor supply.
Similarly, economic growth is ultimately not for the sake of economic growth but for the sake of job creation, enhancing return on investments and/or forestalling a breakdown of social stability. As Simon Kuznets pointed out long ago, the organic analogy of "growth" is a poor fit for economic activity because what "grows" is not an organism or a population of like organisms but an artificial index of successive, non-identical composites of diverse goods and services.
One might say, however, that economic growth is for the sake of population growth and population growth is for the sake of economic growth (which is for the sake of population growth… ad infinitum). This circular reasoning more closely fits an earlier formulation of Abbey's maxim: "They cannot see that growth for the sake of growth is a cancerous madness, that Phoenix and Albuquerque will not be better cities to live in when their populations are doubled again and again." In other words, the motivation for growth is delusional; the consequence is malignant.
What makes Abbey's metaphorically-dubious proposition curiously apt is that the core propositions of market fundamentalism are themselves dubious, question-begging metaphors: "survival of the fittest," "competitive equilibrium," "tragedy of the commons," and "man's triumph over nature." In a recent article, "Karl Polanyi’s Genealogy of Utopian Liberalism," Christopher England examined the ideology that emerged in the late 18th century regarding the political aspects of population and poverty with particular attention to Polanyi's analysis of that literature in The Great Transformation.
Although commonly attributed to Malthus, the core arguments and naturalistic, pseudo-scientific framing trace back to Joseph Townsend's 1786 tract, "A Dissertation on the Poor Laws by a Well-Wisher to Mankind." In that tract, Townsend recounted – and embellished -- a story about goats and dogs on one of the Juan Fernandez islands in the South Pacific off the coast of Chile to illustrate his contention that society would be best served by leaving poor people to the discipline of the labor market and the perils of starvation.
According to the account of Jorge Juan and Antonio de Ulloa, upon which Townsend relied, the explorer Juan Fernandez left goats on the island as provision for subsequent voyages. The goats propagated freely until the viceroy of Peru dispatched a colony of dogs to the island in an attempt to eradicate the goats lest they furnish provisions to enemy ships or pirates. Instead of totally eliminating the goats, however, the dogs only succeeded in making the goats scarcer, "the dogs being incapable of pursuing them among the fastnesses where they live, these animals leaping from one rock to another with surprising agility" according to Juan and Ulloa. Townsend elaborated:
Had they been totally destroyed, the dogs likewise must have perished. But as many of the goats retired to the craggy rocks, where the dogs could never follow them, descending only for short intervals to feed with fear and circumspection in the rallies, few of these, besides the careless and the rash, became a prey; and none but the most watchful, strong, and active of the dogs could get a sufficiency of food. Thus a new kind of balance was established. The weakest of both species were among the first to pay the debt of nature; the most active and vigorous preserved their lives.Thus Juan and Ulloa's sparse account of a standoff between dog and goat populations was transformed by Townsend into a morality tale about survival of the fittest of the two populations. Why Townsend's fable was as persuasive to audiences as Polanyi and England contend it was is a long story best told by those two authors.
The short version is that people are distressed by scenes of suffering and welcome solace in the thought that either the hardship is deserved punishment for some earlier transgression or that it will eventually be compensated by future reward. Reward and punishment bestow an aura of meaning to the otherwise inexplicable suffering.
The technical term for this kind of sadistic wishful thinking is "theodicy" and it became a staple of orthodox political economy. The corollary to the stoic justification of other people's misery is, of course, the axiom that public actions intended to alleviate suffering will invariably, as Townsend put it, "promote the evils they mean to remedy, and aggravate the distress they were intended to relieve." Analyses that refute these baleful platitudes have a way of being forgotten or even reformulated to conform to the conventional framework.
Townsend deftly fused the punishment and reward poles of the theodicy loophole, reproaching the drunkenness, profligacy, indolence, dishonesty of the poor such that, "[i]t seems to be a law of nature, that the poor should be to a certain degree improvident, that there may always be some to fulfil the most servile, the most sordid, and the most ignoble offices in the community."
It is good the poor are reduced to such wretchedness. "The stock of human happiness is thereby much increased," Townsend continued, "whilst the more delicate are not only relieved from drudgery, and freed from those occasional employments which would make them miserable, but are left at liberty, without interruption, to pursue those callings which are suited to their various dispositions, and most useful to the state." Such a philosophical outlook!
If that cheerful state of affairs is not enough, consider the benefits the prospect of starvation confers on the poor themselves: "Hunger will tame the fiercest animals, it will teach decency and civility, obedience and subjection, to the most brutish, the most obstinate, and the most perverse." Hunger is the most equitable, effectual and suitable method for instructing the dishonest or neglectful worker that "the first duty required from a servant is prompt, chearful, and hearty obedience."
The survival of the fittest theodicy has been refuted, only to have the refutation subsequently misrepresented as a confirmation. A prime example of this recuperation trick is the fate of William Forster Lloyd's "Two Lectures on the Checks to Population" from 1833. Those lectures contained the image Garrett Hardin made famous 135 years later as the "Tragedy of the Commons." Hardin misinterpreted and/or misrepresented the point of Lloyd's image. Lloyd compared the field for employment of labor to an unregulated commons as a rebuttal to the Malthus/Townsend hypothesis that the prospect of starvation could act as a check to unsustainable growth of population. On the contrary, Lloyd maintained, the dynamics of overgrazing an unregulated commons would act as a perverse incentive to do exactly that. Lloyd's suggested remedy was a sort of endowment, modeled on customs in Norway, to encourage young people to postpone marriage until they have accumulated a sufficient nest egg.
Lloyd maintained that some inequality of wealth was necessary to provide incentives but that, contrary to Townsend's doctrine, extreme inequality was not only ineffectual but detrimental. Hardin's reinterpretation of the tragedy of the commons, however, reverts back to Townsend's conclusions about individual suffering providing a check to population while collective provision would encourage profligacy and indolence -- precisely the conclusions that Lloyd's model repudiated.
Seventy-five years ago, Karl Polanyi laid out what was at stake in the contest between fascism, socialism and liberalism. Whether his conclusions ring true today is an open question. But the historical insight that brought him to those conclusions is essential to understanding our present predicament -- perhaps more urgent now than ever.
Christopher England's essay explicates what Polanyi saw as "the mind's ambivalent response" of "unbounded hope and limitless despair," which constituted "the mainspring of the metaphysical forces that secretly sustained the positivists and utilitarians." England defined that ambivalent response as reflecting a "theodicy of economic life":
[Polanyi's] reading of the Speenhamland debacle shows that in asking the question provoked by poverty -- “Where do the poor come from?” -- the unspoken issue at stake is what the late Peter Berger calls the ancient core of theodicy: “Why does God permit some men to eat and others to go hungry?” This dilemma is, in turn, tied up with an even thornier issue, “Why do we suffer?” With the arrival of industrial society and the reconceptualization of the economy as the focal point of political life, the old theological questions took on an economic guise. A new style of political economy came to the fore, imbued with an acute sense of desperation and a theoretical framework capable of justifying dramatic political action.Voltaire ridiculed theodicy in Candide, published in 1759, the year after Juan and Ulloa's account of the goats and dogs was translated into English. Candide's tutor, Dr. Pangloss, a philosophical charlatan, repeated his "optimistic" nostrum at every opportunity:
“It is demonstrable,” said he, “that things cannot be otherwise than as they are; for as all things have been created for some end, they must necessarily be created for the best end. … they, who assert that everything is right, do not express themselves correctly; they should say that everything is best.”When Candide later encounters a syphilis-ravaged Pangloss, the latter rationalizes his condition as "a thing unavoidable, a necessary ingredient in the best of worlds." He later asserts the necessity of misfortune, “for private misfortunes are public benefits; so that the more private misfortunes there are, the greater is the general good.”
Adam Smith's Theory of Moral Sentiments appeared in the same year as Candide. In it, Smith told the tale of the "poor man's son, whom heaven in its anger has visited with ambition." This young man, "feels himself naturally indolent, and willing to serve himself with his own hands as little as possible; and judges, that a numerous retinue of servants would save him from a great deal of trouble…." Thus he embarks on a life of toil and stinginess to accumulate the wealth that will enable him to someday live in luxurious sloth. Alas, he is deceived:
…in the last dregs of life, his body wasted with toil and diseases, his mind galled and ruffled by the memory of a thousand injuries and disappointments which he imagines he has met with… that he begins at last to find that wealth and greatness are mere trinkets of frivolous utility, no more adapted for procuring ease of body or tranquility of mind than the tweezer-cases of the lover of toys.However, Smith rationalized this outcome with an optimistic paradox: "And it is well that nature imposes upon us in this manner. It is this deception which rouses and keeps in continual motion the industry of mankind." Smith celebrated as a spur to industry the theodicy Voltaire had mocked.
There was nothing natural or inevitable about the institutionalization of this economic theodicy. As Polanyi pointed out 75 years ago:
Economic history reveals that the emergence of national markets was in no way the result of the gradual and spontaneous emancipation of the economic sphere from governmental control. On the contrary, the market has been the outcome of a conscious and often violent intervention on the part of government which imposed the market organization on society for noneconomic ends.Over the last 40 years there has again been "conscious and often violent intervention" by governments to impose market discipline on society. We are reaping the harvest of that intervention today in the accumulation of greenhouse gas emissions, the uprooting of populations, the abject dismantling of social trust and the proliferation of reactionary Malthusian populisms. The cancer has metastasized.
We were warned. My intuition tells me there is no digging out of the hole the death spasm of Utopian [neo]Liberalism has dug us into – "because races condemned to one hundred years of solitude did not have a second opportunity on earth." Setting aside fantasies of a magical, dialectical cure ("arise, ye prisoners of starvation… "), our best hope is for palliative care. A start would be to eradicate every vestige of economic theodicy (or any theodicy for that matter) from our public discourse. That won't be easy. It probably can't be done. But it gives us something useful to do other than passively watching civilization collapse.
I was unaware of this aspect of Abbey and have no comment on him specifically.
ReplyDeleteHowever, in this time when environmentalism is widely viewed as "left" against obvsious "right" anti-environmentalism (especially on the climate issue), it is easy to forget that older views of all this were more complicated, as the old tradition of "Brown Marsism" on the left partly shows.
The other side was (is in some places and the writings of the El Paso shooter) is indeed ugly, racist eco-fascism, literally. Most do not know that Hitler himself was viewed as an environmentalist ("conswevtionist" in those days), with a "blood and soil" view that opposes supposedly evil cosmopolite urban people against the "true German race" living in the rural areas, this is hard stuff. We saw this in the USSR when the original environmentalist movement in the 70s, inspired to help preserve Lake Baikal from industrial pollution, was led by right-wing anti-Semitic Russian nationalists. There is an old and ugly tradition to this stuff.
What I am interested in here is what eco-fascism has in common with market fundamentalism. Nobody gets out of this one unscathed.
ReplyDeleteBTW, Barkley, while researching this, I came across reference to an old article by you, "A Reconsideration of Marx's Critique of Malthus's Principle of Population." (1979) Would you happen to have an electronic copy of that you could send me?
Soory, no electronic copy for that oldie but goody, which is indeed relevant to all this. I am in Wisconsin now visiting family. Will have to get back to office to see if I can find a hard copy of it. I do have one somewhere in my mess.
ReplyDeleteThanks.
ReplyDeleteA brilliant essay; wow.
ReplyDelete@The Sandwichman
ReplyDeleteour best hope is for palliative care
These are not rhetorical questions:
(1) Are you fully aware of what palliative care entails?
(2) Do you really mean it?
Don't get me wrong, I'm not disputing your conclusion (nor am I endorsing it for that matter), I just want to understand exactly what your conclusion is.
The RED Herring
RED Herring,
ReplyDeleteYes, I know what palliative care entails and yes...
I am not convinced the supposed essay is authentic. I an seeing anachronistic language for 1988.
ReplyDelete@The Sandiwchman,
ReplyDeleteI will be very honest and I hope you won't take this in a bad way.
I also hope I'm just being a fool and people will laugh at my concern, but I find your answer (which I thank) deeply unsettling, for what it says about your appreciation of our current situation and for what it suggests about your own emotional state.
I will beg of you to reconsider things, for our collective and your personal good.
The RED Herring
RED,
ReplyDeleteDon't worry about me. I feel very positive. My social diagnosis may well be wrong and I would advise readers to get a second opinion. I just don't see any political initiatives current or on the horizon that are equal to the task.
My interpretation is that Abbey was a curmudgeon and contrarian whose intended target was liberal hypocrisy. Immigrants were merely "collateral damage" of his colorful diatribes....
ReplyDelete[ I have never heard or read the name, Abbey, and need a reason why I should care at all about such a person. Why would I learn about and possibly mention such a person in a lecture? My instinct after reading this post is avoid knowing about the person entirely.
Obviously I am missing the purpose here. ]
Obviously, I don't care whether or not you care at all about Edward Abbey.
ReplyDeleteI used Abbey as the personalizing scaffold for my essay because he was a superb, compelling writer who saw the intimate connection between economic growth and migration but who expressed it regressively.
What's the actual connection? Overpopulation is necessary for the realization of surplus value by capital. In the Grundrisse, Marx wrote:
"Labour capacity can perform its necessary labour only if its surplus labour has value for capital, if it can be realized by capital. Thus, if this realizability is blocked by one or another barrier, then (1) labour capacity itself appears outside the conditions of the reproduction of its existence; it exists without the conditions of its existence, and is therefore a mere encumbrance; needs without the means to satisfy them; (2) necessary labour appears as superfluous, because the superfluous is not necessary. It is necessary only to the extent that it is the condition for the realization of capital. Thus the relation of necessary and surplus labour, as it is posited by capital, turns into its opposite, so that a part of necessary labour – i.e. of the labour reproducing labour capacity – is superfluous, and this labour capacity itself is therefore used as a surplus of the necessary working population, i.e. of the portion of the working population whose necessary labour is not superfluous but necessary for capital."
When remembered at all, Edward Abbey is mostly thought of as an environmentalist and anarchist but there is no gainsaying the racism and xenophobia on display in his 1983 essay...
ReplyDelete[ When a person is presented as being thoroughly anti-social, I should be able to ask why that person should be read. I need a socially compelling reason to read an "anarchist" who was "racist" and "xenophobic."
I have no idea how I manage to offend you, when I try to never be offensive and am always offering praise for your writing.
I am surely entitled to ask about why I should know or care about an anarchist who was racist and xenophobic and who the New York Times could not publish.
I am offended by racism and need a compelling reason to tolerate racism in a writer. Evidently editors of the New York Times decided similarly.
I do appreciate you warning me about the anti-social environmentalist in question.
I meant no offense and appreciate the warning, but so far I am inclined to avoid knowing about the writing of such a person. ]
Obviously, I don't care whether or not you care at all about Edward Abbey....
ReplyDelete[ I surely did not deserve such a mean response. To expose a student to the writing of such an evidently anti-social person, I would need a solid rationale. ]
You don't deserve a mean response? Did you ever wonder whether I deserved to be told that I shouldn't write about people YOU don't want to hear about?
ReplyDeleteYou have an option -- don't read my posts if you find them objectionable or only read the ones you don't find objectionable. I don't mind you objecting to something I wrote but it is condescending when you try to tell me what I should or shouldn't write about.
I happen to appreciate Edward Abbey's writing and quite a bit of his point of view. Part of critical thinking is to parse what is good and what is bad in an author's writing or in an entire field of inquiry.
Ruthless criticism of all that exists. Warts and all. You don't want to see warts? Look away.
Did you ever wonder whether I deserved to be told that I shouldn't write about people YOU don't want to hear about?
ReplyDelete[ I never ever told you any such thing, I only asked why "I" should learn and about about a particular person. I was "not" critical of what you wrote, I found your description of the person off-putting and asked why I should care about a person described in such a way.
Fine, I am an ungrateful fool and regret and apologize for any perceived criticism. I am frightened by racism, but I will learn about the person you introduced me to.
I deeply regret every questioning and perceived critical word I wrote. You are completely right in your writing and I will always be grateful in future.
I am sorry. ]
Perfectly explained; I am so grateful for the remarkable effort:
ReplyDeletehttps://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1857/grundrisse/ch12.htm
Grundrisse
Necessary labour. Surplus labour. Surplus population. Surplus capital
Labour capacity can perform its necessary labour only if its surplus labour has value for capital, if it can be realized by capital. Thus, if this realizability is blocked by one or another barrier, then (1) labour capacity itself appears outside the conditions of the reproduction of its existence; it exists without the conditions of its existence, and is therefore a mere encumbrance; needs without the means to satisfy them; (2) necessary labour appears as superfluous, because the superfluous is not necessary. It is necessary only to the extent that it is the condition for the realization of capital. Thus the relation of necessary and surplus labour, as it is posited by capital, turns into its opposite, so that a part of necessary labour – i.e. of the labour reproducing labour capacity – is superfluous, and this labour capacity itself is therefore used as a surplus of the necessary working population, i.e. of the portion of the working population whose necessary labour is not superfluous but necessary for capital.ars outside the conditions of the reproduction of its existence; it exists without the conditions of its existence, and is therefore a mere encumbrance; needs without the means to satisfy them; (2) necessary labour appears as superfluous, because the superfluous is not necessary. It is necessary only to the extent that it is the condition for the realization of capital. Thus the relation of necessary and surplus labour, as it is posited by capital, turns into its opposite, so that a part of necessary labour – i.e. of the labour reproducing labour capacity – is superfluous, and this labour capacity itself is therefore used as a surplus of the necessary working population, i.e. of the portion of the working population whose necessary labour is not superfluous but necessary for capital.
I deeply regret being foolish and ungrateful. This is all entirely wonderful.
ReplyDeleteYou are wonderful.
Presumably, Abbey did not think of himself as racist. He was indignant when accused of racism. But the institutions of the society he grew up in transmit racism in their DNA.
ReplyDelete[ Importantly enough, the writers I work with and discuss with students managed to avoid "inheriting" racism and this makes them especially encouraging to me and my students.
I tried, really tried, but found the essay savage and stopped reading:
http://www.brontaylor.com/courses/pdf/Abbey--ImmigrationTaboo.pdf
1983
' “The Closing Door Policy,” an essay later revised as “Immigration and Liberal Taboos.” ' ]
http://www.brontaylor.com/courses/pdf/Abbey--ImmigrationTaboo.pdf
ReplyDelete1983
' “The Closing Door Policy,” an essay later revised as “Immigration and Liberal Taboos.” '
[ Forgive me, I tried, but I am unable to read through such an essay. Thank you so very much for your essay, however. ]