The following passage is from a 1993 New Left Review essay, "Political Ecology: Expertocracy versus Self-Limitation," by André Gorz. It is an argument for regenerating a norm of sufficiency as a political project. How much is enough and how can we build a popular consensus and movement around such a determination? Of particular interest to me, in the final paragraph Gorz mentions the "anonymous Ricardoite" along with John Maynard Keynes and Wassily Leontieff as examples of those who have seen disposable time as "the true measure of wealth." That Ricardoite was, of course, Charles Wentworth Dilke who wrote the 1821 pamphlet, The Source and Remedy of the National Difficulites.
Self-Limitation as a Social Project
In complex industrial societies, it is impossible to obtain
an eco-compatible restructuring of production and consumption simply by giving
the workers the right to limit their effort voluntarily (in other words, the
possibility of choosing their working time, the right to ‘chosen time’). There
is in fact no evident correlation between the volume of production and
the hours worked. Once mechanization has abolished this correlation by enabling
more and more goods to be produced with less and less labour, ‘labour ceases to
be the measure of production and working time the measure of labour’ (Marx).
Moreover, the diminution in the volume of labour necessary does not benefit the
potential active population in general, and does not confer emancipation or the
hope of greater autonomy on either the employed or the unemployed. Finally
there exists no commonly accepted norm of sufficiency that could serve as a
reference for self-limitation. Nevertheless, self-limitation remains the only
non-authoritarian, democratic way towards an eco-compatible industrial
civilization.
This project is not absolutely insurmountable. Essentially,
it signifies that capitalism has abolished everything in tradition, in the mode
of life, in everyday civilization, that might serve as anchorage for a common
norm of sufficiency; and has abolished at the same time the prospect that
choosing to work and consume less might give access to a better, freer life.
What has been abolished is not, however, impossible to re-establish. But this
restoration cannot be based on existing traditions and correlations: it has to
be instituted; it is a matter of politics, more exactly a matter of
eco-politics and the eco-social project.
An eco-social politics, as debated at length by the German and other European Greens during the 1980s and now emerging in French political ecology, aims fundamentally to restore politically the correlation between less work and
less consumption on the one hand, and more autonomy and more existential
security on the other, for everyone. In other words, it involves providing individuals with institutional guarantees that a general reduction in working hours will offer everyone the advantages people formerly sought for themselves: a freer, more relaxed and richer life. Self-limitation is thus shifted from the level of individual choice to the level of a social project. The norm of sufficiency, deprived of its traditional mooring, has to be defined politically.
Without going into detail on matters I have discussed at length elsewhere, I would recall here only that eco-social politics consists principally in giving a guarantee of sufficient income, independent of the duration of labour (which can only decrease), and perhaps independent of work itself; redistributing socially necessary labour in such a way that everyone can work (and work both better and less); creating areas of autonomy in which the time freed from labour could be used by individuals for activities of their own choice, including self-production of goods and services which would reduce their dependence on the market and on professional or administrative supervision, permitting them to reconstruct a tissue of known solidarities and social conviviality that would include mutual aid networks, the exchange of services, informal cooperatives, etc. The liberation of time, the liberation of individuals from heteronomous, functionally specialized labour, should be conceived as an overall politics that would also demand fundamental new thinking on architecture, town planning, public equipment and services, relations between town and country, and so on, in order to de-compartmentalize the different spheres of life and activity, and encourage self-organized exchange.
Political ecology thus uses ecologically necessary changes
to the mode of production and consumption as a lever for normatively desirable
changes in the mode of life and in social relations. Defence of the living
environment in the ecological sense, and the reconstitution of a life-world,
condition and support one another. Both require life and the living environment
to be withdrawn from the domination of economics; both require the growth of
spheres of activity to which economic rationality does not apply. This
requirement, in truth, is as old as civilization. From the anonymous Ricardoite whose 1821 pamphlet Marx so
enjoyed quoting to Keynes and Leontieff, the leading theoreticians of modern
economics have all held disposable time for activities ‘valued as an end
in themselves’ (die sich als Selbstzweck gilt, in Marx’s term from the Grundrisse)
to be ‘the true measure of wealth’. This boils down to saying that
economic activity has meaning only if it serves something other than itself.
For economics is a clear example of ‘cognitive-instrumental reasoning’: a
science for calculating the effectiveness of means, and selecting the most
effective means to achieve a given end. It cannot be applied to ends which are
not distinct from the means employed, and cannot in itself determine what ends
should be pursued. When it is not supplied with an end, it chooses those ends
for which it possesses the most effective means: it will adopt as a target the
expansion of the sphere in which its own rationality applies, and will tend to
subject to this sphere all others, including life and the natural foundations
of life.